The law of irreversibility of evolution is explained. The law of the irreversibility of evolution explained at the molecular level The law of the irreversibility of evolution by ldall

The evolutionary process is characterized by irreversibility. The position on the irreversibility of evolution was first formulated in 1893 by the Belgian paleontologist L. Dollo (1857-1931). The essence of this provision, later calleddollo law, is thatthat organisms, moving into their former habitat, do not completely return to the previous state of morphophysiological organization. Thus, the gills and fins of fish, lost by their tetrapod descendants, were never restored in reptiles and mammals that re-assimilated the aquatic lifestyle (the caudal fin and flippers of ichthyosaurs and cetaceans only superficially resemble the fins of fish, with a profound difference in their internal structure). The irreversibility of evolution is a statistical pattern arising from the improbability of a complete return to the previous (ancestral) state of a set of processes realized in the genotype and phenotype of a particular group of organisms.

The evolution of structures is based on the processes of differentiation and integration. Principle of differentiation established in 1851 by the French zoologist A. Milne-Edwars (1800-1863),principle of integration first described by G. Spencer (1820-1903).Morphophysiological differentiation is the development in the process of evolution from one structure of several different-quality structures that perform different, narrower (private) functions. As an example of differentiation, one can cite the division of the originally simply arranged digestive tube (performing a single general function of splitting and absorbing cleavage products) into sections (mouth, pharynx, esophagus, stomach, small and large intestines), in which food is already subjected to specific influences (mechanical processing , chemical breakdown, absorption, etc.).

The process of integration is inextricably linked with differentiation. Integration is the expedient association and coordination of the actions of different parts of an integral living system. If differentiation leads to an increase in the degree of subordination of parts (organs) to the body as an integral system, then integration is manifested in the unification of organs into functionally unified systems that provide one of the aspects of the life of the organism.

The basis of the morphofunctional transformations of individual organs ismultifunctionality (polyfunctionality) - the performance by this body of several functions at the same time, among which one can usually single out the main (main) function and a number of secondary ones. For example, the main function of the swim bladder of ray-finned fish is hydrostatic (regulation of buoyancy by changing volume). Along with this, it is also used as a baroreceptor, signaling the depth of immersion, as an apparatus for transforming sound vibrations, which increases the sensitivity of the hearing organ, and in primitive ray-finned (lobe-finned) it performs the function of a respiratory organ.

Most often, the evolution of organs proceeds in a waychange of functions, in which one of the secondary functions of the organ under the influence of the changed relations of the organism with the external environment becomes more important (main) than the former main function. So, in the ancestors of vertebrates, skin scales in the area of ​​the closing edges of the jaws were transformed into teeth that perform another main function: instead of mechanical protection, the function of capturing, holding and crushing food. In plants, for example, the petals of the corolla of a flower evolved from leaves that changed the function of photosynthesis to the function of attracting insects for pollination. The change of functions was first described by the German zoologist Anton Dorn (1840-1909). The ability to change functions is based on the multifunctionality of organs. When a function is changed, the direction of evolutionary transformations changes accordingly, sincenatural selection improves the structure of an organ, primarily in relation to its main function.

The transformation of the functions of organs in phylogenesis can also occur in a way of expanding functions. The expansion of functions is

Rice. 160. Evolution of the Vertebrate Heart:

1 - two-chambered heart of fish; 2 - three-chambered heart of amphibians; 3 - a three-chambered heart of reptiles with an incomplete septum in the ventricle; 4 - four-chambered heart of mammals; P - atrium; G - stomach

in the acquisition by an organ (structure) in the course of evolution of new functions while maintaining existing ones. The expansion of functions was first described in 1912 by the German zoologist L. Plate (1862-1937). For example, in warm-blooded animals, the circulatory system is involved in the regulation of heat exchange with the environment; in mammals, it also acquires the function of providing immunity. L. Plate described another way of evolutionary transformations of organs- intensification, or strengthening of functions. Its essence liesin the increase in the course of evolution of the number of functional units and the corresponding complication of the structure of the organ. As examples, we can consider the complication of the structure of the heart (two-chamber, three-chamber, four-chamber) and the intensification of its functions (Fig. 160), the complication of the structure of the brain and the intensification of the functions of the central nervous system.

Two methods of transformation during the evolution of organs (substitution of functions, separation of functions) were described in 1931 by A.N. Severtsov (1866-1936). Substitution of functions (heterotopic substitution) is the loss in the course of evolution of one of the functions and its replacement by another, biologically equivalent, but already performed by another organ located in a different place. For example, the function of moving through the limbs is replaced in snakes by moving with the help of bending of the spine (crawling), breathing with the help of gills (extracting O 2 from water) in terrestrial vertebrates is replaced by gas exchange in the lungs. The division of functions is accompanied by the division of the body into independent departments. So, a single unpaired fin was divided in fish (Fig. 161) into dorsal and anal (rudders), as well as caudal (propulsion).

Rice. 161. Scheme of division of a single unpaired fin in fish

The second type of substitution- substitution of organs (homotopic substitution), described by the German zoologist N. Kleinenberg (1842-1897). Its essence isin the replacement of one organ by another, carrying a similar function and occupying the same position (the notochord, for example, is replaced by a cartilaginous skeleton, and the latter by a bony spine).

To consider the transformation of the structure as memorized, it is sufficient to preserve its consequences during one elementary link in development (three successive states of the system). In a long process of development, these elementary links overlap each other: the states of the system that are part of one link can form, with the states of the links next to them, the previous and the next, four different types of combinations, such that each of them remains an elementary link in development.

Structure, by definition, has holistic properties. This means that any memorized new formation is mediated by all the former properties of the structure that were not forgotten during the selection operation, and all preserved properties of the structure turn out to be mediated by the new formation. In other words, the new formation in the process of memorization becomes an integral aspect (and not part) of this choice - the result of a synthesis of the old and the new. Preservation of the memorized during one elementary link of development affects the outcome of at least two acts of choice that are not included in this elementary link of development and following it. These considerations are invariant for any elementary link in development and for a sequence of overlapping (by one or two states of the system) links of arbitrary length. Hence the conclusion follows: the consequences of this act of remembering will not be equal to zero, and the given aspect of memory that has arisen as a result of this act will not be completely forgotten after any predetermined finite number of elementary links of development (changes of states). The sequence of such elementary steps of development is the own internal time of the developing object

The opposite is tantamount to a break in continuity between the past and the future. Complete oblivion of the consequences of only one act of memorization is tantamount to the destruction of the choice corresponding to it - the state of the structure in the past development of the system. Consequently, the existence of a developing structure at any given moment of time is determined not only by the succession of all the previous states taken together, but also by each of them separately, which is a link between the previous and subsequent states.

Thus, we have obtained a formal conclusion of L. Dollo's position on the indestructibility of the past. Other aspects of the irreversibility of evolution, arising from the rules of phylogenesis considered earlier, are less powerful and only additionally confirm the conclusion about the indestructibility of the past. However, let's list them. Destabilization, without which the emergence of the new is impossible, is associated with at least partial oblivion of the past. If oblivion affects unique information that is not stored after it in the system in any copy, then due to the principle of irreplaceability of completely lost information by A. A. Lyapunov, such a loss is fundamentally irreversible. Since the amount of novelty available for acquisition by the system is proportional to the amount forgotten by it, the more new the system has received, the more irreversible, other things being equal, the development process that led to this will turn out to be.

Any move in the direction of progressive specialization is safer, and therefore more likely, than any change in the direction of specialization. Reversing the direction of development is no exception, although the possibility of extensive use of past experience facilitates a change in the direction of specialization. Therefore, the phenomena of neoteny and fetalization are widespread in phylogenesis. However, the use of previous experience testifies not to the reversibility of development, but to its continuity. You can use only not forgotten experience. The rules of key aromorphosis, monophyly, parallelism, homological and heterological series by E. D. Cope make one think about the scale of the successive transmission of latent potencies and doubt the validity of the statement about the complete irreducibility of completely atrophied organs. It suffices to recall examples of atavisms, among which there are signs that are completely lost in the norm. Many striking examples of this kind (for example, in the bone skull of a person) are cited by A.P. Bystrov. As for the reversibility of evolution, it certainly does not exist, since in these cases there is no reversion even of the structure of the skull, let alone of the entire organization.

L. Dollo and his followers believed that the irreversibility of evolution is based on a very low probability of a strictly step-by-step reverse process - involution. The formal conclusion we have obtained testifies to the deterministic nature of L. Dollo's law. Indeed, if development is a stochastic process, then the development trajectory that has already been realized is the only irreplaceable reality of its kind, the embodiment of which is the current structure of the developing system. This makes it possible to give the status of a law to the irreversibility of development, highlighting it among other empirical rules of phylogenesis.

There are three most famous formulations of L. Dollo's law. The first belongs to C. Darwin: a species that once disappeared cannot appear again, even if completely identical conditions would repeat again - organic and inorganic. Two other formulations belong to L. Dollo: 1) the organism cannot return (at least partially) to the previous state, which was carried out in the series of its ancestors; 2) the organism never returns exactly to its previous state, even if it finds itself in conditions of existence identical to those through which it passed; but due to the indestructibility of the past, he always retains a trace of the intermediate stages that he passed through.

Almost all objections to the strict application of the principle of irreversibility concerned the formulations of L. Dollo, and not C. Darwin. D. N. Sobolev believed that the facts of despecialization contradict the irreversibility of evolution. Obviously here we are talking about the reversibility of the level of specialization to certain limits, and not development. It is no coincidence that in this connection Sobolev writes about the reversibility of ontogeny. In unicellular organisms, we are talking about despecialization, while in multicellular organisms, it is about continuity. There is no true reversibility of ontogeny. This is also indicated by the laws of K. Baer and the equifinality of ontogenesis. When D. N. Sobolev writes about the widespread reverse evolutionary development and the return of the group to the starting point of development, it is always about the phenomena of iterative evolution, neoteny or fetalization. Obviously, the very fact of such "reversibility" can be established morphologically only because of its incompleteness. True, D.N. Sobolev, being a paleontologist, at least in principle could judge the reversibility of identical direct and reversible phylogenetic series, using their gradualness and independently (more precisely, quite independently, especially when it comes to ammonites) this scale of geological time. However, he never relies on a purely stratigraphic succession, and all forms of the "reverse" series receive taxonomic names, and most importantly, diagnoses different from those of the direct series. In the case of sufficiently complete reversibility, the position of V.P. Makridin, who questioned the principle of irreversibility in the formulation of C. Darwin, would be more consistent. Moreover, assuming that reversibility can be of jump-identical direct and reverse phylogenetic series, true reversibility and reject the hypothesis of long-term persistence of the ancestral form along with progressively developing descendants. Moreover, neontologists, a number of whom made similar judgments, could not empirically detect complete reversibility.

Some of the considerations similar to those described were also expressed by P. P. Sushkin. It is no coincidence that he believed that evolution is reversible insofar as ontogeny is similar to phylogeny. Here again, the continuity observed during hypogenesis is meant, and not true reversibility. Being a good embryologist, P. P. Sushkin undoubtedly meant incomplete reversibility. but main feature position of P. P. Sushkin, as well as many other researchers, is the opposition of the strict irreversibility of the organization of the whole organism to the possible reversibility of individual, especially simple signs. Even for relatively simple combinations of simple features, P. P. Sushkin considered reversibility less likely. This position, where the reversibility of an individual, arbitrarily selected from the whole feature, the probability of reversibility of which as a member of the ensemble decreases, can appear, obviously has an epistemological character. The law of irreversibility in this case acquires a probabilistic character not as a result of the probabilistic nature of the irreversibility of evolution itself as an ontological phenomenon, but due to the probabilistic nature of any historical reconstructions and, in general, any empirical judgments based on limited material. Such an approach to the problem of reversibility is quite justified, since evolution, like any reality, is not available for a specific study in the fullness and diversity of its manifestations. We are fully aware that a fundamental solution to the problem of the irreversibility of development leaves many epistemological problems (reversibility at a certain level).

In the latter case, we are not talking about evolution itself and its irreversibility, but about the possibilities, methods and limits of its cognition empirically. It is the ontological side that has always been the main one in discussions around Dollo's law.

L. Dollo himself felt the incompleteness of the purely empirical justification of his law, he even tried to give him a theoretical deductive justification. Rightly believing it to be non-rigorous, P. P. Sushkin strove to remain on the basis of reliable empirical facts. This was the basis of his criticism of Dollo's law. But at the same time, P.P. Sushkin did not notice that he was no longer discussing evolution, but our ability to judge it on the basis of empirical data. Indeed, this ability turned out to be limited, which is in good agreement with the opinion of L. Dollo about the incompleteness of the empirical justification of the law.

If we turn to the ontological aspect of the meaning of the term "feature", namely in this sense we use it when we try to judge evolution itself (and not the ways of its cognition), we immediately find the opposition of the part to the whole in the approach of P. P. Sushkin. Obviously, speaking of reversibility, it is supposed to compare two states of a feature. The identification of features means the establishment of their homology. For this, homology criteria are used. In this case, we are interested in the criterion of the position of a feature as a part or aspect of the whole (meron) in its relationship (connection) to other features of the same whole. Without using this criterion, it is impossible to establish the place of the meron in the archetype, and therefore, to compare the corresponding features as merons. In fact, R. Owen wrote about this. Such an attitude towards a trait is in good agreement with the idea of ​​the organism as a whole, in which each part or aspect is mediated by the whole. Consequently, the opposition of an individual feature to an ensemble of features or to the whole (quite acceptable as a methodological device) in the ontological approach not only contradicts the principle of integrity, but is illegal from a purely morphological point of view: without being able to compare features as such (establish their homology), we cannot judge about their identity, and hence reversibility. From this point of view, the first of L. Dollo's formulations of the law of irreversibility, which met with the greatest number of objections, turns out to be correct.

Thus, the main objections to the law of irreversibility of evolution are reduced to the following.

1. Repetition (usually far from complete) of signs, based on which the opponents themselves see continuity, and not reversibility. This is evidenced by the interpretation of these cases as iterative evolution, neoteny, fetalization or atavisms.

2. The reversibility of the level of specialization, and not of phylogenesis as such.

3. Repetition of an organization or part of it only at a given, arbitrarily chosen level of consideration (for example, at a given level of knowledge). In fact, the repetition is not complete, which usually follows from an analysis of the technique used by the opponent. Usually the very fact of reversibility cannot be empirically established if it is sufficiently complete.

4. Statement of the impossibility or extreme difficulty of empirically demonstrating the irreversibility of each individual feature (which is especially important for a paleontologist with his always defective material).

Thus, the first three objections are based on methodological miscalculations at the level of interpretation of empirical data; the latter is based on a mixture of the ontological and epistemological aspects of the problem. Without belittling the relevance and complexity of the latter, we believe that they are not directly related to evolution.

To content:

an organism (population, species) cannot return to its former state, which was in the series of its ancestors, even after returning to their habitat. It is possible to acquire only an incomplete number of external, but not functional, similarities with their ancestors. The law (principle) was formulated by the Belgian paleontologist Louis Dollo in 1893.

  • - evolutionary irreversibility - The pattern of evolutionary development, which consists in the impossibility of returning completely to the ancestral state: the principle of N. e. formulated by L. Dollo in 1893...
  • - causal chain leading the shortest way to changes in the living from simple to complex, from less adapted to more adapted, prohibiting other directions of development ...

    The Beginnings of Modern Natural Science

  • - A hypothesis put forward in 1890 by the paleontologist Louis Dollo, according to which features or functions that have disappeared during the process of evolution cannot reappear in a given ...

    Physical Anthropology. Illustrated explanatory dictionary

  • - the law formulated by the Belgian Darwinist paleontologist L. Dollo, according to which evolutionary processes are irreversible, the body cannot return to its previous state, already ...

    Ecological dictionary

  • - the law formulated by P. Dansero, according to which a part of renewable natural resources can become exhaustible, non-renewable, if a person with irrational agricultural, ...

    Ecological dictionary

  • - see Dollo's Law...

    Ecological dictionary

  • - see Dollo's Law...

    Ecological dictionary

  • - the pattern of history. development of organisms, manifested in the fact that organisms, moving into their former habitat, do not completely return to their ancestral state ...

    Biological encyclopedic Dictionary

  • - Dollo's rule - The concept that within each evolutionary branch the evolutionary process is irreversible - for example, the evolution of birds will never lead to the appearance of Archeopteryx ...

    Molecular biology and genetics. Dictionary

  • - the regularity of phylogenesis: organisms, returning in the process of evolution to the habitat of distant ancestors, cannot become absolutely similar to them. So, the ichthyosaurs, secondarily adapted to life in the water, did not become ...

    Natural science. encyclopedic Dictionary

  • - syn. term law of irreversibility of evolution...

    Geological Encyclopedia

  • - rather, the rule formulated by Bela, the paleontologist Dollo; once an organ or trait lost in the phylogenetic series is not restored in the process of further phylogenetic development ...

    Geological Encyclopedia

  • - see Art. Dollo's law...

    Ecological dictionary

  • - Belgian paleontologist, foreign corresponding member of the Academy of Sciences of the USSR. He studied the morphological features of fossil animals associated with their way of life. The main work "Ecological paleontology" ...
  • - DOLLO law - a pattern of phylogenesis: organisms, returning in the process of evolution to the habitat of distant ancestors, cannot become absolutely similar to them. So, secondarily adapted to life in the water ...

    Big encyclopedic dictionary

  • - evolution pl. 1. Various kinds of movements associated with moving, rebuilding someone or something. 2. Rebuilding during the movement of troops from one formation to another. 3...

    Explanatory Dictionary of Efremova

"Dollo's Law of Irreversibility of Evolution" in books

From the book Evolution author Jenkins Morton

BIOGENETIC LAW AS EVIDENCE OF EVOLUTION

From the book Evolution author Jenkins Morton

BIOGENETIC LAW AS EVIDENCE OF EVOLUTION The similarity in the development of vertebrate embryos prompted scientists to half of XIX century to a thorough study of this issue. For the first time, the existence of a connection between the development of the embryo and the species was suggested by the famous embryologist Karl

Chapter 11 Vermey's Law of the Consequences of Evolution and How Snakes Shaped the World Imagine that everything in the world has suddenly changed. Imagine that you are able to see smaller and more distant objects than you see now. Imagine that your sense of smell is incredible

2.5.2. THE LAW OF KARMA IN HUMAN EVOLUTION

From the book Spiral of Knowledge: Mysticism and Yoga of the author

2.5.2. THE LAW OF KARMA IN HUMAN EVOLUTION The Law of Karma is one of the Laws of the Cosmos, outside the scope of which there is not a single phenomenon, not a single object, not a single being. The word pocket, from which the name of the law is derived, has a number of meanings in Sanskrit, namely:

The law of evolution and the law of God

From the book Ask and Receive author Morancy Pierre

The Law of Evolution and the Law of God The sixth and seventh laws of the tao of business concern the conscious decision to leave our earthly paradise. Therefore, they will not be discussed in this

27. Is there a law of evolution? Laws and trends

From the book The Poverty of Historicism author Popper Karl Raimund

Giuseppe Balsamo and the problem of the irreversibility of time

From the book Journey Through the Ages [Memoirs of Count Cagliostro and recordings of his conversations with Aristotle, Dante, Pushkin, Einstein and many other contemporaries] author Kuznetsov Boris Grigorievich

Giuseppe Balsamo and the Problem of the Irreversibility of Time It is time, however, to tell about the trips to the 18th century, which were mentioned in the introductory essay, and which allowed me to become Count of Cagliostro. I knew that this was a historical figure, I knew that his real name was Giuseppe Balsamo.

Chapter One The Law of Human Intellectual Evolution or the Law of Three Stages

From the book The Spirit of Positive Philosophy author Comte Auguste

CHAPTER ONE THE LAW OF INTELLECTUAL EVOLUTION OF MANKIND, OR THE LAW OF THREE STAGES 2. According to my basic doctrine, all our speculations, both individual and generic, must inevitably pass through three distinct theoretical stages in succession, which can be

Once again about irreversibility

From the book Secrets of Space and Time the author Komarov Victor

Once again about irreversibility It is curious that almost all the laws of modern physics do not theoretically prohibit the reversal of those processes that are practically irreversible.

Point of no return

From the book The Story of an Accident [or The Descent of Man] author Vishnyatsky Leonid Borisovich

Point of no return Above, we tried to find out the main causes and approximate time of the beginning of the first cultural revolution. It was also said that its main result was the transformation of culture into a factor that determines the most important aspects of the behavior of human ancestors and

Dollo law

TSB

Dollo Louis

From the book Great Soviet Encyclopedia (DO) of the author TSB

The second law of thermodynamics refutes the theory of evolution

From the book Proving the Existence of God. Arguments of science in favor of the creation of the world the author Fomin A V

The second law of thermodynamics refutes the theory of evolution The law of thermodynamics states that natural conditions always lead to disorder. The theory of evolution is a scientifically unfounded scenario that is completely contrary to this law. "The second law

1.1. Basic law of evolution

From the book Phenomenon of Science. Cybernetic approach to evolution author Turchin Valentin Fedorovich

1.1. The Basic Law of Evolution In the process of evolution of life, as far as we know, there has always been and is now an increase in the total mass of living matter and the complication of its organization. Complicating the organization of biological formations, nature acts according to the method of trials and

Using the example of the evolution of the glucocorticoid receptor (GR), a protein that controls the response of cells to the "stress hormone" cortisol, it was possible to show how evolutionary changes can become irreversible. GH acquired its current function, along with losing the previous one, over 400 million years ago as a result of the replacement of only two key amino acids. This change is completely reversible. However, during the subsequent evolution of the receptor, many additional mutations accumulated in it, which slightly improved the performance of the new function, but completely deprived the protein of the opportunity to return to its original state.

The "law" of the irreversibility of evolution ("Dollo's law") was formulated as early as the 19th century and has since been repeatedly discussed by theoretical biologists and philosophers. Such discussions usually remain speculative and rely on general philosophical ideas and selected examples from paleontology and comparative anatomy ("some terrestrial vertebrates returned to the water, but did not turn back into fish - therefore, evolution is irreversible"). Meanwhile, this question is important for understanding such a basic characteristic of evolution as the ratio in it of “random”, caused by a combination of circumstances (including the evolutionary history of the organism), and “natural”, dictated by the requirements of expediency (adaptation). If any evolutionary change could be easily reversed, then natural selection - the only factor that gives evolutionary changes "meaningfulness" (adaptive direction) - could quickly and efficiently optimize the structure of organisms, "adjusting" them to environmental conditions, without any regard on their previous evolutionary history. The irreversibility of most evolutionary changes, on the contrary, would indicate that the evolutionary history of organisms imposes severe restrictions on the possibilities of their further evolution. Meanwhile, it is very difficult to realistically assess the degree of irreversibility of one or another evolutionary event in practice.

Joseph W. Thornton of the University of Oregon and his colleagues, using the example of the evolution of the vertebrate glucocorticoid receptor (GR), clearly demonstrated how and why evolutionary changes occurring at the level of a single protein molecule can become irreversible. The researchers used a whole arsenal of the latest methods. They began by comparing the amino acid sequences of 60 different steroid hormone receptors found in modern organisms. They reconstructed the evolutionary history of GR and restored the amino acid sequence of this protein as it was at the most important nodes (branch points) of the vertebrate evolutionary tree.

It turned out that key events in the evolution of GRs occurred over 400 million years ago and were confined to the segment between two nodes of the tree, corresponding to: 1) the separation of the ancestors of cartilaginous fish and all other jawed vertebrates; 2) separation of the lines of ray-finned and lobe-finned fishes (the ancestors of the latter are also the ancestors of all terrestrial vertebrates).

The recovered amino acid sequences corresponding to these two nodes were named AncGR1 and AncGR2, respectively. The first squirrel was in the last common ancestor of all jawed-stomes (the jawed-stomes include cartilaginous fish, bony fish and their descendants - terrestrial vertebrates, they are also tetrapods). The owner of the second protein was the last common ancestor of all bony fish and tetrapods, who lived 40 million years later.

The authors then artificially synthesized the GR genes that these long-extinct ancestors should have had, and made them work in Chinese hamster cell culture. Together with the “resurrected” GR genes, a genetic construct was introduced into the cells, containing the gene for the luciferase enzyme borrowed from fireflies (see: reporter gene assays). The regulatory region of this gene was designed in such a way that luciferase synthesis depended on GR activity. As a result, it was possible to evaluate the effectiveness of the response of GR to certain steroid hormones by the strength of the glow. The spatial structure of the "resurrected" GRs was studied using X-ray diffraction analysis (see X-ray crystallography).

The first part of the results obtained was published two years ago in the journal Science (Ortlund et al., 2007. Crystal Structure of an Ancient Protein: Evolution by Conformational Epistasis // Science. V. 317. P. 1544-1548; full text - PDF, 410 Kb). It turned out that the AncGR1 protein was a relatively weakly specialized receptor that responded to a wide range of so-called mineralocorticoids, including aldosterone and deoxycorticosterone. This receptor also responded to cortisol, but much weaker. The AncGR2 protein, on the contrary, was a specialized receptor that selectively responds to cortisol (as well as modern human and other terrestrial vertebrate GRs).

The change in receptor function during the transition from AncGR1 to AncGR2 was associated with the replacement of 37 amino acids in the region of the protein molecule responsible for steroid hormone binding. The scientists found that two of the 37 substitutions played a key role in the change in function (see figure). The first of these (replacement of serine (S) with proline (P) at position 106; designated S106P) changed the configuration of the active center of the protein molecule in such a way that the amino acid located at position 111 was next to the unique hydroxyl group of cortisol, which is absent in other steroid hormones. The second substitution (L111Q) occurred exactly at the 111th position and led to the fact that the cortisol molecule began to attach to the active center of GR by an additional hydrogen bond. Subsequently, three more substitutions occurred that enhanced the new function of GH (selective binding of cortisol), reducing its affinity for mineralocorticoids. These three substitutions, however, also reduced the stability of the spatial configuration of the protein molecule. In order for these three substitutions to take hold, two more substitutions had to occur, which the authors called "permissive" in the sense that they smoothed out the harmful effects of other substitutions and allowed them to gain a foothold in the course of natural selection.

Thus, to change the function of GH, a total of 7 amino acid substitutions were required - two "key", three "optimizing" and two "allowing". The authors experimentally showed that if the appropriate 7 changes are made to the AncGR1 protein, the protein acquires a new function (that is, it begins to selectively bind cortisol and ceases to respond to mineralocorticoids). Such a protein (AncGR1 with seven substitutions) functions almost in the same way as AncGR2, which, as we remember, differs from AncGR1 not by seven, but by 37 substitutions. The remaining 30 substitutions appear to be either neutral (i.e. fixed by chance as a result of genetic drift) or they contributed to the optimization of the new structure and function of the protein, but only to a very small extent.

V new job, published in the latest issue of the journal Nature, the authors showed that some of these 30 "not very necessary" substitutions, which the GH protein could well do without, had an important side effect. As it turned out, they closed the possibility for the protein to return to its original function, that is, they made the change that occurred earlier evolutionarily irreversible.

Natural selection cannot see into the future. It cannot commit a deleterious mutation just because it will turn out to be beneficial later, when the next mutation is fixed. Therefore, only such evolutionary trajectories are possible, in which each single step is either useful here and now, or, at worst, neutral. As long as GR's new function was provided by only the seven amino acid substitutions discussed above (two "key", three "optimizing" and two "permissive"), the evolution of GR could still be reversed. To do this, it would be enough to change the direction of selection. For example, ancient vertebrates - the ancestors of bony fish and tetrapods - would suddenly benefit from having their GR begin to react again to mineralocorticoids. In this case, "optimizing" mutations could first return to their original state. This would lead to a slight increase in the sensitivity of GH to mineralocorticoids, and therefore such a change could be supported by selection. In the future, one would expect the reversal of two "key" mutations - this would lead to a complete restoration of the previous function.

As we already know, if seven mutations are introduced into the AncGR1 protein, it changes its function: it begins to selectively respond to cortisol and ceases to pay attention to mineralocorticoids. It is clear that if you return these seven amino acids to their original state, the protein will return to its original function. At this stage, evolution is still reversible. However, when the authors returned the same seven amino acids in the AncGR2 protein to their original state, no return to the previous function occurred. Instead, it turned out to be a completely useless protein that did not respond to either cortisol or mineralocorticoids. The reason, obviously, lies in those 30 "extra" mutations that distinguish AncGR2 from AncGR1.

The authors conducted a comprehensive analysis of these 30 amino acid substitutions and concluded that at least five of them interfere with the return of the protein molecule to the original spatial configuration required for mineralocorticoid binding. The "benefit" of these substitutions, apparently, was not very much: they only slightly increased the stability of the new configuration necessary for cortisol binding. But they are nevertheless fixed, because natural selection "sees" only a momentary benefit, albeit a small one, and cannot even look one step ahead. Thus, cutting off the path to retreat - a kind of evolutionary burning of bridges - turned out to be accidental. side effect small, secondary evolutionary "work" to optimize the new function.

The return of these five mutations to their original state is extremely unlikely, because the body does not receive any instant benefit from such a return: the new function begins to perform a little worse, the old one is not restored. And until these five mutations return to their original state, it remains impossible (= definitely harmful) to reverse the seven amino acid substitutions that provided the change in protein function.

How many interesting opportunities have been irretrievably lost in the course of evolution due to the "short-sightedness" of its main manager - natural selection? There is no exact answer to this question yet, but it is possible that there were much more lost opportunities than realized ones.

THE LAW OF IRREVERSIBILITY OF EVOLUTION is rather a rule formulated by Bela, the paleontologist Dollo (1893); an organ once lost in the phylogenetic series or not restored in the process of further phylogenetic development. Currently, a partial return to the ancestral state is allowed, associated with the transition to the previous way of life. However, completely lost structures and the reappearance of ancestral species are ruled out. Synonym: Dollo's law.

Geological dictionary: in 2 volumes. - M.: Nedra. Edited by K. N. Paffengolts et al.. 1978 .

See what the "LAW OF IRREVERSIBILITY OF EVOLUTION" is in other dictionaries:

    THE LAW OF IRREVERSIBILITY OF EVOLUTION Ecological dictionary

    THE LAW OF IRREVERSIBILITY OF EVOLUTION- according to this law, the organism never returns to the previous state, already realized in a number of its ancestors ... Glossary of botanical terms

    Dollo's law of irreversibility of evolution- an organism (population, species) cannot return to its previous state, which was in the series of its ancestors, even after returning to their habitat. It is possible to acquire only an incomplete number of external, but not functional, similarities with their ancestors. Law… … Beginnings of modern natural science

    Law (principle) of irreversibility of evolution- * law (pryntsyp) of non-evolutionary evolution * law of evolution irreversibility ... Genetics. encyclopedic Dictionary

    THE RULE OF IRREVERSIBILITY OF EVOLUTION- see Dollo's Law. Ecological encyclopedic dictionary. Chisinau: Main edition of the Moldavian Soviet Encyclopedia. I.I. Grandpa. 1989... Ecological dictionary

    Syn. term law of irreversibility of evolution. Geological dictionary: in 2 volumes. M.: Nedra. Edited by K. N. Paffengolts et al. 1978 ... Geological Encyclopedia

    LAW DOLLO- the law formulated by the Belgian paleontologist Darwinist L. Dollo (1893), according to which evolutionary processes are irreversible, an organism (population, species) cannot return to the previous state already implemented in a number of its ancestors. It should… … Ecological dictionary

    environmental law- a set of fundamental provisions of ecology and nature management. Environmental laws and rules were generalized and consolidated into a single system by N.F. Reimers, according to whom ecological laws are theorems that can be proven ... human ecology

    - (the law of the irreversibility of evolution), the regularity of phylogenesis: organisms, returning in the process of evolution to the habitat of distant ancestors, cannot become absolutely similar to them. So, ichthyosaurs, secondarily adapted to life in water, did not become ... ... Natural science. encyclopedic Dictionary

    The law of the irreversibility of evolution, first clearly formulated in 1893 by the Belgian paleontologist L. Dollo. According to Dollo, an organism cannot return, even partially, to the previous state, which has already been passed by a number of its ancestors. For instance … Great Soviet Encyclopedia